The Metaphysics and Ethics of the Jainas

Published: 16.09.2011
Updated: 02.07.2015


The article was first published in Transactions of the 3rd International Congress for the History of Religions (Vol. 2, Oxford 1908, pp. 59-66) and reissued later in the miscellany volume Studies in Jainism (Allahabad 1946, pp. 48-60). To make this online reissue citeable, the page numbers are added to the text (see squared brackets).

 

The Metaphysics and Ethics of the Jainas

[59] All who approach Jain philosophy will be under the impression that it is a mass of philosophical tenets not upheld by one central idea, and they will wonder what could have given currency to what appears to us an unsystematical system. I myself have held, and given expression to, this opinion, but I have now learned to look at Jain philosophy in a different light. It has, I think, a metaphysical basis of its own, which secured it a distinct position apart from the rival systems both of the Brahmans and of the Buddhists. This is the subject on which I would engage your attention for a short space of time.

Jainism, at least in its final form, which was given it by its last prophet the twenty-fourth Tīrthaṅkara Mahāvīra, took its rise, as is well known, in that part of Eastern India where in an earlier period, according to the Upaniṣads, Yājñavalkya had taught the doctrine of Brahman and Ātman, as the permanent and absolute Being, and where Mahāvīra's contemporary and rival, Gotama the Buddha, was preaching his Law, which insisted on the transitoriness of all things. Jainism, therefore, had to take a definite position with reference to each of these mutually exclusive doctrines; and these it will be necessary to define more explicitly.

The one great Truth which the authors of the Upaniṣads thought to have discovered, and which they are never weary of exalting, is that, underlying and upholding from within all things, physical as well as psychical, there is one absolute permanent Being, without change and with none other like it. The relation between this absolute Being and existent matter has not clearly been made out by the authors of the Upaniṣads, but all unprejudiced readers will agree that they looked on the phenomenal world as real. On this point the different schools of Vedāntins arrived at different conclusions, which, however, need not detain us here.

In opposition to this Brahmanical doctrine of absolute and permanent Being, Buddha taught that all things are transitory; indeed his dying words were, that all things that are produced must perish. The principal heresy, according to the Buddhists, is the Ātmavāda, i.e. the belief that permanent Being is at the bottom of all things; they are, as we should say, but phenomena, or as Buddha expressed [59|60] it, dharmas; there is no dharmin, no permanent substance of which the dharmas could be said to be attributes.

Thus the Brahmans and the Buddhists entertained opposite opinions on the problem of Being because they approached it from two different points of view. The Brahmans exclusively followed the dictates of pure reason which forces us to regard Being as permanent, absolute, and uniform; the Buddhists, on the other hand, were just as onesided in following the teaching of common experience according to which existence is but a succession of originating and perishing. Either view, the a priori view of the Brahmans, and the a posteriori view of the Buddhists, is beset with many difficulties when we are called upon to employ it in explanation of the state of things as presented to us by our consciousness; difficulties which cannot be overcome without a strong faith in the paramount truth of the principle adopted.

The position taken by the Jainas towards the problem of Being is as follows. Being, they contend, is joined to production, continuation, and destruction (sad utpāda-dhrauvya-vināśa-yuktam), and they call their theory the theory of indefiniteness (anekāntavāda), in contradistinction to the theory of permanency (nityavāda) of the Vedāntists, and to the theory of transitoriness (vināśavāda) of the Buddhists. Their opinion comes to this. Existing things are permanent only as regards their substance, but their accidents or qualities originate and perish. To explain: any material thing continues for ever to exist as matter; which matter, however, may assume any shape and quality. Thus clay as substance may be regarded as permanent, but the form of a jar of clay, or its colour, may come into existence and perish.

The Jain theory of Being appears thus to be merely the statement of the common-sense view, and it would be hard to believe that great importance was attached to it. Still it is regarded as the metaphysical basis of their philosophy. Its significance comes out more clearly when we regard it in relation to the doctrines of Syādvāda, and of the Nayas.

Syādvāda is frequently used as a synonym of Jainapravacana (e.g. at a later date in the title of a well-known exposition of the Jain philosophy entitled Syādvāda-Mañjarī); and it is much boasted of as the saving truth leading out of the labyrinth of sophisms. The idea underlying the Syādvāda is briefly this. Since the nature of Being is intrinsically indefinite and made up of the contradictory attributes of originating, continuance, and perishing, any proposition about an existing thing must, somehow, reflect the indefiniteness of Being, i.e. any metaphysical proposition is right from one point of view, and the contrary proposition is also right from another. There [60|61] are, according to this doctrine, seven forms of metaphysical propositions, and all contain the word syāt, e.g. syād asti sarvam, syād nāsti sarvam. Syāt means 'may be', and is explained by kathacit, which in this connexion may be translated 'somehow'. The word syāt here qualifies the word asti, and indicates the indefiniteness of Being (or astitvam). For example, we say, a jar is somehow, i.e. it exists, if we mean thereby that it exists as a jar; but it does not exist somehow, if we mean thereby that it exists as a cloth or the like.

The purpose of these seeming truisms is to guard against the assumption made by the Vedāntins that Being is one without a second, the same in all things. Thus we have the correlative predicates 'is' (asti) and 'is not' (nāsti). A third predicate is 'inexpressible' (avaktavya); for existent and non-existent (sat and asat) belong to the same thing at the same time, and such a coexistence of mutually contradictory attributes cannot be expressed by any word in the language. These three predicates variously combined make up the seven propositions or saptabhangas of the Syādvāda. I shall not abuse your patience by discussing this doctrine at length; it is enough to have shown that it is an outcome of the theory of indefiniteness of Being (anekāntavāda), and to have reminded you that the Jainas believe the Syādvāda to be the key to the solution of all metaphysical questions.

The doctrine of the Nayas which I mentioned before is, as it were, the logical complement to the Syādvāda. The nayas are ways of expressing the nature of things: all these ways of judgement are, according to the Jainas, one-sided, and they contain but a part of the truth. There are seven nayas, four referring to concepts, and three to words. The reason for this variety is that Being is not simple, as the Vedāntins believe, but is of a complicated nature; therefore, every statement and every denotation of a thing is necessarily incomplete and one-sided; and if we follow one way only of expression or of viewing things, we needs must go astray.

There is nothing in all this which sounds deeply speculative; on the contrary, the Jain theory of Being seems to be a vindication of common-sense against the paradoxical speculations of the Upaniṣads. It is also, but not primarily, directed against the Buddhistic tenet of the transitoriness of all that exists. We cannot, however, say that it expressly and consciously combats the Buddhistic view, or that it was formulated in order to combat it. And this agrees well with the historical facts, that Mahāvīra came long after the original Upaniṣads, but was a contemporary of Buddha. He was obliged, therefore, to frame his system so as to exclude the principles of Brahmanical speculation, but his position was a different one with regard to the newly proclaimed system of Buddha. [61|62]

I have not yet touched on the relation between Jain philosophy on the one hand and Sānkhya-Yoga on the other. We may expect a greater community of ideas between these systems, since both originated in the same class of religious men, viz. the ascetics known as the Śramaas, or, to use the more modern term, Yogins. As regards the practice of asceticism, the methods and the aim of Yoga, it has long been proved that the Yoga of Brahmans, Jainas, and Bauddhas are closely related to each other, and there can be no doubt that they have all developed from the same source. But I am now concerned only with those philosophical ideas which have a connexion with ascetic practice and form the justification thereof.

Now the Sānkhya view as to the problem of Being is clearly a kind of compromise between the theory of the Upaniṣads and what we may call the common-sense view. The Sānkhyas adopt the former with regard to the souls or puruas which are permanent and without change. They adopt the latter when assigning to matter or Prakti its character of unceasing change. The Sānkhyas contend that all things besides the souls or puruṣas are products of the one Prakṛti or primaeval matter, and similarly the Jainas teach that practically all things besides the souls or jīvas are made up of matter or pudgala, which is of only one kind and is able to develop into everything. It will thus be seen that the Sānkhyas and Jainas are at one with regard to the nature of matter; in their opinion matter is something which may become anything. This opinion, it may be remarked, seems to be the most primitive one; not only was it entertained by the ancients, but also it underlies the universal belief of transformation occurring in the natural course of things or produced by sorcery and spells. This is a point I wish to make, that the Sānkhyas and Jainas started from the same conception of matter, but worked it out on different lines.

The Sānkhyas teach that the products of Prakṛti are evolved in a fixed order, from the most subtle and spiritual one (Buddhi) down to the gross elements, and this order is always reproduced in the successive creations and dissolutions of the world. The Jainas, on the other hand, do not admit such a fixed order of development of matter (pudgala), but believe that the universe is eternal and of a permanent structure. According to them matter is atomic, and all material changes are really going on in the atoms and their combinations. A curious feature of their atomic theory is that the atoms are either in a gross condition or in a subtle one, and that innumerable subtle atoms take up the space of one gross atom. The bearing of this theory on their psychology I shall now proceed to point out. But I must premise that the Jainas do not recognize a psychical apparatus of such a complex nature as the Sānkhyas in their tenet concerning Buddhi, Ahakāra, Manas, and the Indriyas. The Jaina [62|63] opinion is much cruder, and comes briefly to this.

According to the merit or demerit of a person, atoms of a peculiar subtle form, which we will call karma matter, invade his soul or jīva, filling and defiling it, and obstructing its innate faculties. The Jainas are quite outspoken on this point, and explicitly say that karman is made up of matter, paudgalika karma. This must be understood literally, not as a metaphor, as will be seen from the following illustrations. The soul or jīva is extremely light, and by itself it has a tendency to move upwards (ūrdhvagaurava), but it is kept down by the karma matter with which it is filled. But when it is entirely purged of karma matter, at Nirvāṇa, it goes upwards in a straight line to the top of the universe, the domicile of the released souls.

To take another example. The karma matter within a soul may assume different conditions. It may be turbulent, as mud in water which is being stirred; or it may be inactive, as mud in water when it has settled at the bottom of a basin; or it may be completely neutralized as when the clear water is poured off after the mud has been precipitated. Here again it is evident that karma is regarded as a substance or matter, though of an infinitely more subtle nature than the impurities of water referred to in the illustration. As a third instance I will refer to the six Leśyās or complexions of the souls, ranging from deepest black to shining white, colours which we common mortals cannot perceive with our eyes. This doctrine was shared also by the Ājīvikas, on whom Dr. Hoernle [1] has thrown so much light. These colours of the soul are produced on it by the karman which acts as a colouring substance. Here also the material nature of karman is quite obvious.

To return from this digression, the karma matter that enters the soul is transformed into eight different kinds of karman, about which I shall have to say a word presently. This change of the one substance into eight varieties of karman is likened to the transformation of food consumed at one meal into the several fluids of the body. The karma matter thus transformed and assimilated builds up a subtle body, which invests the soul and accompanies it on all its transmigrations, till it enters Nirvāṇa and goes up to the top of the universe. This subtle body or kārmaaśarīra is obviously the Jain counterpart of the sūkmaśarīra or lingaśarīra of the Sānkhyas. [2]

In order to understand the functions of this subtle body or kārmaṇaśarīra, we must take a summary view of the eight kinds of karman of which it is composed. The first and second (jñānāvaraṇīya and darśaāvaraṇīya) obstruct knowledge and faith, which are innate faculties of the soul or jīva; the third (mohanīya) causes delusion, especially [63|64] the affections and passions; the fourth (vedanīya) results in pleasure and pain; the fifth (āyuka) assigns the length of life to the person in his present birth; the sixth (nāma) furnishes him with all that belongs to him as an individual; the seventh (gotra) makes him a member of the class or genus which he is to belong to; the eighth (antarāya) produces hindrances to the realization of his virtues and powers.

Each of these eight kinds of karman endures for a certain period, of varying length, within which it must take its proper effect. Then it is expelled from the soul, a process which is called nirjarā. The opposite process, the influx of karman into the soul, is called āsrava, a term well known to students of Buddhism. The occasions for āsrava are the actions of the body and mind (yoga); they open as it were an inlet for karma matter to invade the soul. If that soul is in a state of iniquity, i.e. if the person under consideration does not possess right faith, or does not keep the commandments (vrata), or is careless in his conduct, or does not subdue his passions, then, in all these cases, singly or collectively, especially under the influence of the passions, the soul must retain the karma matter, or, as the Jainas say, binds it (bandha). But the influx of karma matter or āsrava can be prevented; this is called the stopping or savara.

These primitive notions the Jainas have worked out into a philosophical superstructure, which serves just as well as that of the Sānkhyas (but on different lines) to explain the problems of mundane existence and to teach the way of salvation. In order to make this clear I must add a few more details.

Saṃvara is effected, i.e. the influx of karma is prevented, by the observance of peculiar rules of conduct, by restraint of body, speech, and mind, by strict morality, by religious reflections, by indifference to things pleasant or unpleasant, etc. The most effective means, however, is the practice of austerities (tapas), which has this advantage over the other means, that it not only prevents karma from accumulating, but also consumes the accumulated karma. Tapas, therefore, produces also nirjarā and leads to Nirvāṇa; it is the chief means of salvation, as might be expected in a religion of ascetics.

The denotation of the word 'tapas' in Jainism is somewhat different from its usual meaning. There is tapas of the body (bāhya tapas) and tapas of the mind (ābhyantara tapas). The former consists in fasting, or eating scanty and tasteless food, in want of comfort and in mortification of the flesh. The mental tapas contains various items, as confession of sins and penance, monastic duties, obedience, modesty, self-restraint and meditation (dhyāna). I wish to lay stress on the fact that in the course of asceticism taught by the Jainas meditation is only one of many steps leading to the ultimate goal.

Though Nirvāṇa is immediately preceded by the two purest stages [64|65] of meditation, yet all other parts of tapas appear of equal importance. We shall see the significance of this fact more clearly, when we compare the Jaina tapas with what corresponds to it in Sānkhya-Yoga. Their Yoga contains some of the varieties of Jaina tapas; but they are regarded as inferior to meditation or contemplation. Indeed the whole Yoga centres in contemplation; all other ascetic practices are subordinate and subservient to contemplation - dharanā, dhyāna and samādhi. This is but natural in a system which makes the reaching of the summum bonum dependent on jñāna, knowledge. The theory of the evolution of Prakṛti, beginning with Buddhi, Ahakāra, and Manas, appears, to my mind, to have been invented in order to explain the efficiency of contemplation for acquiring supernatural powers and for liberating the soul.

Sānkhya-Yoga is a philosophical system of ascetics; but their asceticism has been much refined and has become spiritualized in a high degree. The asceticism of the Jainas is of a more original character; it chiefly aims at the purging of the soul from the impurities of karman. Jainism may have refined the asceticism then current in India; it certainly rejected many extravagances, such as the voluntary inflicting of pains; but it did not alter its character as a whole. It perpetuated an older or more original phase of asceticism than the Brahmanical Yoga, and carries us back to an older stratum of religious life in which we can still detect relics of primitive speculation in the shape of such crude notions as I have had occasion to mention in the course of my paper.

In conclusion I shall shortly touch on the third current of Indian philosophical speculation, viz. the philosophy of the Pandits which is represented to us by the Nyāya and Vaiśeṣika systems. This philosophy may be characterized as an attempt to register, to define, and to arrange in systematic order the concepts and general notions which are the common possession of all who spoke the Sanskrit language. Such a philosophy had some attraction for the Jainas who, as we have seen, always sided with common-sense views, and in fact many Jainas have written on Nyāya and Vaiśeṣika. But at the time when the Jain system was framed, the Pandit, as we know him in later times, had probably not yet become distinguished from the Vedic scholar or theologian; it is almost certain that there was as yet no class of persons who could be called Pandits, and consequently their philosophy also was wanting. And the tradition of the Jainas themselves says as much; for according to them the Vaiśeṣika system was founded by Chaluya Rohagutta, originally a Jaina and pupil of Mahāgīri, eighth Sthavira after Mahāvīra. Thus we have no occasion to inquire into the relation between this system and Jainism. But it may be mentioned that the atomic theory which is a marked feature of the Vaiśeṣika, is already taught in outline by the Jainas. [65|66]

As regards the Nyāya system, it is almost certainly later than Jainism; for the dialectics and logic of the Jainas are of a very primitive character, and appear entirely unconnected with the greatly advanced doctrines of the Naiyāyikas.

In conclusion let me assert my conviction that Jainism is an original system, quite distinct and independent from all others; and that, therefore, it is of great importance for the study of philosophical thought and religious life in ancient India. [66]

Footnotes
1:

Jump to occurrence in text

2:

Jump to occurrence in text

Sources

Studies in Jainism (1946)

Edited & corrected version by HN4U

Compiled by PK

Categories

Click on categories below to activate or deactivate navigation filter.

  • Institutions
    • Jainology
      • Ethics and Philosophy
        • Center for Jaina Studies FU Berlin [CfJS.FU], Germany
          • Share this page on:
            Page glossary
            Some texts contain  footnotes  and  glossary  entries. To distinguish between them, the links have different colors.
            1. Allahabad
            2. Anekāntavāda
            3. Antarāya
            4. Asat
            5. Avaktavya
            6. Bandha
            7. Body
            8. Brahman
            9. Buddha
            10. Buddhi
            11. Buddhism
            12. Consciousness
            13. Contemplation
            14. Dhyāna
            15. Fasting
            16. Gotama
            17. Gotra
            18. HN4U
            19. Indriyas
            20. JAINA
            21. Jain Philosophy
            22. Jaina
            23. Jainism
            24. Jñāna
            25. Jñānāvaraṇīya
            26. Jīva
            27. Karma
            28. Karman
            29. Kārmaṇaśarīra
            30. Mahāvīra
            31. Meditation
            32. Mohanīya
            33. Nayas
            34. Nirjarā
            35. Nirvāṇa
            36. Nyāya
            37. Nāma
            38. PK
            39. Pandit
            40. Prakṛti
            41. Pudgala
            42. Sanskrit
            43. Saṃvara
            44. Soul
            45. Space
            46. Studies in Jainism
            47. Syād
            48. Syādvāda
            49. Syāt
            50. Tapas
            51. Tīrthaṅkara
            52. Upaniṣads
            53. Vaiśeṣika
            54. Vedanīya
            55. Vedic
            56. Vrata
            57. Yoga
            58. samādhi
            59. Ābhyantara
            60. Āsrava
            61. Ātmavāda
            Page statistics
            This page has been viewed 4025 times.
            © 1997-2024 HereNow4U, Version 4.56
            Home
            About
            Contact us
            Disclaimer
            Social Networking

            HN4U Deutsche Version
            Today's Counter: